網頁圖片
PDF
ePub 版

DEATH, PUNISHMENT OF.

repel all aggressions by a force or precaution adequate to the object. This results from the right of self-preservation. If a person attempts to take away my life, I have, doubtless, a right to protect myself against the attempt by all reasonable means. If I cannot secure myself but by taking the life of the assailant, I have a right to take it. It would otherwise follow, that I must submit to a wrong, and lose my life, rather than preserve it by the means adequate to maintain it. It cannot, then, be denied that, in a state of nature, men may repel force by force, and may even justly take away life, if necessary to preserve their own. When men enter society, the right to protect themselves from injury and to redress wrongs is transferred, generally, from the individuals to the community. We say that it is generally so, because it must be obvious that, in many cases, the natural right of self-defence must remain. If a robber attacks one on the highway, or attempts to murder him, it is clear that he has a right to repel the assault, and to take the life of the assailant, if necessary for his safety; since society, in such a case, could not afford him any adequate and prompt redress. The necessity of instant relief, and of instant application of force, justifies the act, and is recognised in all civilized communities. When the right of society is once admitted to punish for offences, it seems difficult to assign any limits to the exercise of that right, short of what the exigencies of society require. If a state have a right to protect itself and its citizens in the enjoyment of its privileges and its peace, it inust have a right to apply means adequate to this object. The object of human punishments is, or may be, threefold; first, to reform the offender; secondly, to deter others from offending; and, lastly, to secure the safety of the community, by depriving the offender of the power of doing mischief. The first consideration rarely enters into human legislation, because of the inadequacy of our means to produce great moral results by the infliction of punishment. The two latter considerations enter largely into the theory and practice of legislation. Who is to be the judge, in such cases, what is the adequate punishment for any offence? Certainly, punishments ought not to be inflicted, which are utterly disproportionate to the offence, and beyond the exigencies of society. No government has a right to punish cruelly and wantonly, and from mere revenge; but, still, the discretion must be vested some

141

where, to say what shall be the degree of punishment to be assigned to a particular offence. That discretion must be, from its nature, justly a part of the legislative power, and to be exercised according to the actual state of society. It may, nay, it must be differently exercised in different ages, and in different countries; for the same punishment which, in one age or country, may be sufficient to suppress an offence, or render it comparatively harmless, may, in another age or country, wholly fail of the effect. If mild punishments fail of effect, more severe must be resorted to, if the offence be of a nature which affects society in its vital principles, or safety, or interests. The very frequency of a crime must often furnish a very strong ground for severe punishment, not only as it furnishes proof that the present punishment is insufficient to deter men from committing it, but from the increased necessity of protecting society against dangerous crimes. But it is often said, that life is the gift of God, and therefore it cannot justly be taken away, either by the party himself, or another. If he cannot take it away, he cannot confer that power on others. But the fallacy of this argument is obvious. Life is no more the gift of God than other personal endowments or rights. A man has, by the gift of God, a right to personal liberty and locomotion, as well as to life; to eat and drink and breathe at large, as well as to exist; yet no one doubts that, by way of punishment, he may be confined in a solitary cell; that he may be perpetually imprisoned or deprived of free air, or compelled to live on bread and water. In short, no one doubts that he may be restrained in the exercise of any privileges or natural rights short of taking his life. Yet the reasoning, if worth any thing, extends to all these cases in an equal degree. If, by his crimes, a man may justly forfeit his personal rights, why not his life? But we have seen that it is not true, even in a state of nature, that a man's life may not be taken away by another, if the necessity of the case requires it. Why, then, may not society do the same, if its own safety requires it? Is the safety of one person more important than the safety of the whole community? Then, again, as to a man's inability to confer on others a right which he does not himself possess. Suppose it is so; the consequence which is deduced from this does not, in fact, arise. Blackstone, indeed, in his Commentaries (4 Comment. 8), seems to deduce the right of society to punish capital offences, in

142

DEATH, PUNISHMENT OF.

own free consent, as the necessary and proper basis on which all the rights of such society depend, is, at best, a gratuitous supposition; and it sometimes leads to very incorrect results. It may be added, that the Scriptures most clearly recognize and justify the infliction of capital punishments in certain cases.

certain cases (that is, in cases of mala prohibita, and not mala in se), from the consent of the offenders. The marquis Beccaria, on the other hand, denies that any such consent can confer the right, and therefore objects to its existence. But the notion of consent is, in nearly all cases, a mere theory, having no foundation in fact. If a foreigner comes into a country, and 2. As to the expediency of capital puncommits a crime at his first entrance, it is ishment. This opens a wide field for a very forced construction to say that discussion. Some able men, who do not he consents to be bound by its laws. If a doubt the right, do still deny the expedipirate commits piracy, it is almost absurd ency of inflicting it. It may be admitted, to say that he consents to the right of all that a wise legislature ought to be slow in nations to punish him for it. The true affixing such a punishment to any but and rational ground on which the right very enormous and dangerous crimes. rests, is not the consent of the offender, The frequency of a crime is not, of itself, but the right of every society to protect its a sufficient reason for resorting to such a own peace, and interests, and property, punishment. It should be a crime of and institutions, and the utter want of any great atrocity and danger to society, and right, in other persons, to disturb, or de- which cannot otherwise be effectually stroy, or subtract them. The right flows, guarded against. In affixing punishments not from consent, but from the legitimate to any offence, we should consider what institution of society. If men have a right are the objects and ends of punishment. It to form a society for mutual benefit and is clear that capital punishment can have security, they have a right to punish other no effect to reform the offender himself. persons who would overthrow it. There It may have, and ordinarily does have, the are many cases where a state authorizes effect to deter others from committing a life to be taken away, the lawfulness of like offence; but, still, human experience which is not doubted. No reasonable shows that even this punishment, when man doubts the right of a nation, in a just inflicted for small offences, which are war, especially of self-defence, to repel easily perpetrated, and to which there is force by force, and to take away the lives great temptation, does not always operate of its enemies. And this right is not con- as an effectual terror. Men sometimes fined to repelling present force, but it are hardened by the frequent spectacles extends to precautionary measures, which of capital punishments, and grow indifferare necessary for the ultimate safety of the ent to them. Familiarity deprives them nation. In such a war, a nation may of their horror. The bloodiest codes are justly insist upon the sacrifice of the lives not those which have most effectually of its own citizens, however innocent, for suppressed offences. Besides, public opinthe purpose of ensuring its own safety. ion has great weight in producing the Accordingly, we find that all nations enrol acquittal or condemnation of offenders. militia and employ troops for war, and If a punishment be grossly disproportionrequire them to hazard their lives for the ate to the offence, if it shock human preservation of the state. In these cases, feelings, there arises, insensibly, a sympalife is freely sacrificed by the nation; and thy for the victim, and a desire to screen the laws enacted for such purposes are him from punishment; so that, as far as deemed just exercises of power. If so, certainty of punishment operates to deter why may not life be taken away by way from crimes, the object of the legislature of punishment, if the safety of society is often thus defeated. It may be added, requires it? If a nation may authorize, that a reasonable doubt may fairly be enin war, the destruction of thousands, why tertained, whether any society can lawmay it not authorize the destruction of a fully exercise the power of punishing, besingle life, if self-preservation require it? yond what the just exigencies of that soThe mistake, however, is in supposing that ciety require. On the other hand, a total life cannot be taken away without the abolition of capital punishments would, in consent of the party. If the foregoing some cases at least, expose society to the reasoning is correct, such consent is chances of deep and vital injuries. A man neither supposed nor necessary. In truth, who has committed murder deliberately, the supposition of an original compact has proved himself unfit for society, and between all the persons who are subject regardless of all the duties which belong to the regulations of a society, by their to it. In his case, the lex talionis can

DEATH, PUNISHMENT OF.

hardly be deemed unjust. The safety of society is most effectually guarded by cutting him off from the power of doing further mischief. If his life be not taken away, the only other means left are, confinement for life, or transportation and exile for life. Neither of these is a perfect security against the commission of other crimes, and may not always be within the power of a nation without great inconvenience and great expense to itself. It is true that the latter punishments leave open the chance of reform to the offender, which is, indeed, but too often a mere delusion; but, on the other hand, they greatly diminish the influence of another salutary principle, the deterring of others from committing like crimes. It seems to us, therefore, that it is difficult to maintain the proposition that capital punishments are, at all times and under all circumstances, inexpedient. It may rather be affirmed that, in some cases, they are absolutely indispensable to the safety and good order of society. We should incline to say that, as a general rule, every nation, in its legislation on this subject, must be governed very much by the manners, customs, habits of thinking, and state of opinion, among the people upon whom it is to operate. In a rude and barbarous state of society, summary and almost vindictive punishments seem more necessary than in a highly polished and civilized state of society.

3. As to the crimes to which capital punishments may, most properly, be limited. From what has been already said, this must depend upon the particular circumstances of every age and nation; and much must be left to the exercise of a sound discretion on the part of the legislature. As a general rule, humanity forbids such punishments to be applied to any hut crimes of very great enormity, and danger to individuals or the state. If any crimes can be effectually suppressed by moderate means, these ought, certainly, to be first resorted to. The experience, however, of most nations, if we may judge from the nature and extent of their criminal legislation, seems to disprove the opinion so often indulged by philanthropists, that moderate punishments are sufficient to suppress crimes, and that capital punishments are rarely necessary. The codes of most civilized nations abound with capital punishments. That of Great Britain, a nation in which the public legislation has a deep infusion of popular opinion, is thought to be uncommonly sanguinary. Blackstone, in his Commen

143

taries (vol. iv, 18), admits that, in his time, not less than one hundred and sixty crimes were, by the English law, punishable with death. In the code of the U. States, only nine crimes are so punishable, viz., treason, murder, arson, rape, robbery of the mail, fraudulent casting away ships, rescue of criminals capitally convicted during execution, and piracy, one species of which is the African slave-trade. In the codes of the several states of the Union, still fewer crimes are generally punishable with death. It remains yet to be proved, whether the general mildness of our penal code has afforded us any greater security against crimes than exists in other nations. Hitherto, the temptations to commit them have been less here, than in other countries less abundantly and cheaply supplied with the necessaries of life. It is still a question, fit to exercise the solicitude and ingenuity of our statesmen and philanthropists, whether we can safely carry on so mild a system in a more corrupt and dense state of society. If we can, it must be by a very sparing use of the power of pardoning; so that the certainty of absolute, unmitigated punishment shall follow upon the offence. Beccaria, with his characteristic humanity and sagacity, has strongly urged that the certainty of punishment is more important to deter from crimes than the severity of it. At present, there is great danger that the pardoning power, in our free forms of government, will, in a great measure, overthrow this salutary principle. Its exercise, therefore, ought to be watched with the greatest jealousy and care, lest the abuse of it should lead to the introduction cither of absolute impunity for offences, or of more extensive capital punishments. It will probably be found, from the experience of most nations, that capital punishment ought not wholly to be dispensed with. On the other hand, it may be safely affirmed, that there is no positive necessity to apply it to a very large number of crimes. Treason, murder, arson, piracy, highway robbery, burglary, rape, and some other offences of great enormity, and of a kindred character, are not uncommonly punished in this manner; but beyond these, it is extremely questionable whether there is any necessity or expediency of applying so great a severity. Still, however, as has been already intimated, much must depend upon the opinion and character of the age, and the prevailing habits of the people, and upon the sound exercise of legislative discretion. What may be deemed uselessly severe in one

144

PUNISHMENT OF.

DEATH, age or country, may be positively required by the circumstances of another age or country.

4. As to the manner of inflicting the punishment of death. This has been different in different countries, and in different stages of civilization in the same countries. Barbarous nations are generally inclined to severe and vindictive punishments, and, where they punish with death, to aggravate it by prolonging the sufferings of the victim with ingenious devices in cruelty. And even in civilized countries, in cases of a political nature, or of very great atrocity, the punishment has been sometimes inflicted with many horrible accompaniments. Tearing the criminal to pieces, piercing his breast with a pointed pole, pinching to death with redhot pincers, starving him to death, breaking his limbs upon the wheel, pressing him to death in a slow and lingering manner, burning him at the stake, crucifixion, sawing him to pieces, quartering him alive, exposing him to be torn to pieces by wild beasts, and other savage punishments, have been sometimes resorted to for the purposes of vengeance, or public example, or public terror. Compared with these, the infliction of death by drowning, by strangling, by poisoning, by bleeding, by beheading, by shooting, by hanging, is a moderate punishment. In modern times, the public opinion is strongly disposed to discountenance the punishment of death by any but simple means; and the infliction of torture is almost universally reprobated. Even in governments where it is still countenanced by the laws, it is rarely resorted to; and the sentence is remitted, by the policy of the prince, beyond the simple infliction of death. In Prussia, where atrocious criminals are required, by the penal code, to be broken upon the wheel, the king always issues an order to the executioner to strangle the criminal (which is done by a small cord not easily seen) before his limbs are broken. So, in the same country, where larceny, attended with destruction of life, is punished by burning alive, the fagots are so arranged as to form a kind of cell, in which the criminal is suffocated by the fumes of sulphur, or other means, before the flame can reach him. In England, in high treason, the criminal is sentenced to be drawn to the gallows, to be hanged by the neck, and cut down alive, to have his entrails taken out and burned while he is yet alive, to have his head cut off, and his body divided into four parts, and these to be at the king's

disposal. But, generally, all the punishment is remitted by the crown, except the hanging and beheading; and when it is not, by connivance of the officers, the criminal is drawn on a hurdle to the place of execution, and is not disembowelled until actually dead. In other cases, the punishment is now simply by hanging, or, in the military and naval service, by shooting. In France, formerly, the punishment of death was often inflicted by breaking the criminal on the wheel. (Damiens was torn to pieces by horses, after he had been tormented with red-hot pincers, and had suffered other horrid tortures.) The usual punishment now is beheading by the guillotine. In cases of parricide, the criminal is conducted, barefooted, and covered with a black veil, to the place of execution, where his right hand is cut off just before he is beheaded. In Austria, the general mode of punishment is by hanging. In Prussia, hanging is rarely inflicted; but the usual punishment is beheading with a heavy axe, the criminal's head being first tied to a block. In other German states, the uncertain mode of execution by the sword still exists. Sand was executed in this manner. It should be remarked, however, that, in Germany, hanging has always been deemed the most infamous sort of punishment; and the sentence has often been commuted for beheading by the sword, as a milder mode of punishment. In the U. States of America, hanging is the universal mode of capital punishment; and, indeed, the constitution of the U. States contains a provision, declaring that "cruel and unusual punishments shall not be inflicted." In China, murderers are cut to pieces; robbers, not. In Russia, the punishment of death has been frequently inflicted by the knout. In Turkey, strangling, and sewing the criminal up in a bag, and throwing him into the sea, are common modes of punishment. In the Roman code, many severe and cruel punishments were prescribed. During the favored times of the republic, many of these were abolished or mitigated. But again, under the emperors, they were revived with full severity. In the ancient Grecian states, the modes of punishment were also severe, and often cruel. But the most general mode of punishment, in ordinary cases, seems, both in Greece and Rome, to have been by hanging. Whether the ancient Greek mode of capital punishment, by taking poison at such hour as the condemned party should choose, has ever been adopted in any modern nation, we

DEATH, PUNISHMENT OF-DEBTOR AND CREDITOR.

are unable to say. As far as we have been able to learn, it is not in use among any Christian people; and the idea of suicide connected with it would probably prevent any such nation from adopting it. Whether executions ought to be in public or in private, has been a question much discussed, and upon which a great diversity of opinion exists among intelligent statesmen. On the one hand, it is said that public spectacles of this sort have a tendency to brutalize and harden the people, or to make them indifferent to the punishment; and the courage and firmness, with which the criminal often meets death, have a tendency to awaken feelings of sympathy, and even of admiration, and to take away much of the horror of the offence, as well as of the punishment. On the other hand, it is said that the great influence of punishment, in deterring others from the like offence, cannot be obtained in any other way. It is the only means to bring home to the mass of the people a salutary dread and warning; and it is a public admonition of the certainty of punishment following upon crimes. It is also added, that all punishments ought to be subjected to the public scrutiny, so that it may be known that all the law requires, and no more, has been done. If punishments were inflicted in private, it could never be known whether they were justly and properly inflicted upon the persons condemned; or whether, indeed, innocent persons might not become the victims.

In England, the court before which the trial is had, declares the sentence, and directs the execution of it; and its warrant is a sufficient authority to the proper officer to execute it. In the courts of the U. States, there is a like authority; but in the laws of many of the states, there is a provision that the execution shall not take place except by a warrant from the governor, or other executive authority. In cases of murder and other atrocious crimes, the punishment in England is usually inflicted at a very short interval after the sentence. In America, there is usually allowed a very considerable interval, varying from one month to six months. In England and America, there lies no appeal from the verdict of a jury and the sentence of a court, in capital cases. In France, there may be a review of it in the court of cassation. (q. v.) In Germany, there is, in criminal as in civil cases, a right of appeal; hence, in that country, few innocent persons have suffered capitally since the 16th century; and in England 13

VOL. IV.

145

and America, the very fact that the verdict and sentence are final, produces great caution and deliberation in the administration of criminal justice, and a strong leaning towards the prisoner on trial. Capital punishment cannot be inflicted, by the general humanity of the laws of modern nations, upon persons who are insane or who are pregnant, until the latter are delivered and the former become sane. It is said that Frederic the Great required all judgments of his courts, condemning persons to death, to be written on blue paper; thus he was constantly reminded of them as they lay on his table among other papers, from which they were readily distinguished. He usually took a long time to consider such cases, and thus set an excellent example to sovereigns of their duty.

DEATH-WATCH; a species of termes, so called on account of an old superstition that its beating or ticking in a sick room is a sure sign of death.

DEBENTURE. (See Drawback.)

DEBT, NATIONAL. (See National Debt.) DEBTOR AND CREDITOR, LAWS OF. One of the first steps, in a community, towards industry and wealth, is the institution of the individual right to property. The guarantee of the individual's earnings to himself is the strongest stimulus to his exertions; and this measure is so obvious, and the one in which every member of a community has so evident an interest, that it is of universal adoption among rude as well as civilized nations, and even precedes the establishment of a regular government; for men will sell, and, as far as they are able, enforce their exclusive right to the fruits of their own labor, before they are in a condition to establish general laws. But, though this principle is so obviously just, and of so early adoption, its extension and application to complicated affairs, and various species of property, and divisions, and modifications of rights to, and interest in, possessions of all sorts, are among the most difficult subjects of legislation. The right of property being once established, the conditions on which the owner will part with and transfer it are, as a natural and necessary consequence, left to his own determination, with some few exceptions ; especially one usually made in favor of the government, or, rather, of the whole collective community, who reserve the right of taking individual property for the public use, without the consent of the proprietor, and upon such terms as the government itself shall prescribe. But, even in this case, a debt or obligation on the

« 上一頁繼續 »